Skip to main content

Abhava, Millnong project, abstraction: descriptions and negation

In the Square of Oppositions conference last month in Lebanon, Mihir Chakraborty considered absence to understand negation and as a positive concept. The idea is central to the notion of abhava in Indian logic. Then there are objects and absences of objects over which, supposedly, once could quantify. I asked him how close Abhava was from a Meinongian theory of objects. His first reaction was to say that to think of the absence of something as an object was not a Meinongian move. In fact, it could seem that one can refer to absences using the original objects - and not descriptions - allowing them to have a modally open horizon of life (as I defined previously in this blog (for example, http://anarchai.blogspot.com.br/2011/06/open-horizon-of-life-and-absolute-other.html and http://anarchai.blogspot.com.br/2011/06/challenges-for-millnong-project.html). The name of an absence would be designed through the name of the lacking object. If this were so, I thought absences could be a way to implement the Millnong project - the project of combining Meinong and Mill by considering non-existing objects as independent from descriptions.

However, this individualization procedure would fail precisely because in this case there is no concretude: the absence of a book on the table is also the absence of a pad on the table unless I describe it one way or another. Nothing can then come and upset my modal tales about how the absence of the book would be if something else were the case. The absence of the book would be necessarily such absence - no modally open horizon. Absence of objects are like mathematical objects - utterly Meinongian in the sense of fully dependent on descriptions. No trace of the independent life that concretude can provide.

Interestingly, Juan Manuel Benitez had discussed, minutes earlier, Buridan´s octagon of oppositions. From a nominalist point of view, predicates should also not be devoid of the modally open horizon of life: they are not associated to descriptions and, viewing them as concrete universals, one could quantify over them. So if being mortal is an object, one can quantify over it and say, for example, being some mortal or being every mortal. (Then, clearly, instead of an A proposition, s is P, we have at least two, s is all P and s is some P.) However negation introduces abstraction and makes it impossible for something to carry on enjoying the modally open horizon: when we say s is no P, we would be close to the notion of absence. And, unless absence can be thought somehow not in purely Meinongian terms (which would amount to the Millnong project), descriptions would have to be fully brought in. It seems that a theory of descriptions is a chapter of a theory of negation.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Hunky, Gunky and Junky - all Funky Metaphysics

Been reading Bohn's recent papers on the possibility of junky worlds (and therefore of hunky worlds as hunky worlds are those that are gunky and junky - quite funky, as I said in the other post). He cites Whitehead (process philosophy tends to go hunky) but also Leibniz in his company - he wouldn't take up gunk as he believed in monads but would accept junky worlds (where everything that exists is a part of something). Bohn quotes Leibniz in On Nature Itself «For, although there are atoms of substance, namely monads, which lack parts, there are no atoms of bulk, that is, atoms of the least possible extension, nor are there any ultimate elements, since a continuum cannot be composed out of points. In just the same way, there is nothing greatest in bulk nor infinite in extension, even if there is always something bigger than anything else, though there is a being greatest in the intensity of its perfection, that is, a being infinite in power.» And New Essays: ... for there is nev...

Memory assemblages

My talk here at Burque last winter I want to start by thanking you all and acknowledging the department of philosophy, the University of New Mexico and this land, as a visitor coming from the south of the border and from the land of many Macroje peoples who themselves live in a way that is constantly informed by memory, immortality and their ancestors, I strive to learn more about the Tiwas, the Sandia peoples and other indigenous communities of the area. I keep finding myself trying to find their marks around – and they seem quite well hidden. For reasons to do with this very talk, I welcome the gesture of directing our thoughts to the land where we are; both as an indication of our situated character and as an archive of the past which carries a proliferation of promises for the future. In this talk, I will try to elaborate and recommend the idea of memory assemblage, a central notion in my current project around specters and addition. I begin by saying that I ...

The underground of concepts: my talk at the Marxism and the Pittsburgh School Conference

In few minutes I'll be presenting this talk in the Marxism and the Pittsburgh School conference in the UCL. I can still change the text but this is how it looks like now. The underground of concepts: McDowell on the productivity of Anschauungen Hilan Bensusan 1. Jean-François Lyotard diagnosed the idea that concepts do the productive work of thinking as a deception. It is not through a dynamics of concepts that conclusions are reached and it is not with the decisive intervention of them that conflicts between alternatives resolved. Lyotard compares the pretense that concepts think with the mystification that capital works. He argues that “what works is not the concept, […] the concept is [like] capital which pretends to work, but which [only] determines the conditions of labour, delimits the outsides and insides, the authorized and the prohibited” (Lyotard, Libidinal Economy, p. 13). This diagnosis, frequently lost in the middle of an ampler argumentation around t...